期刊文献+

Marx on Nature

Marx on Nature
原文传递
导出
摘要 Ecological Marxists argue that Marx forged a view of nature compatible with more recent models of environmentalism. John Bellamy Foster argues that Marx ascribed an ecological value to nature by asserting a co-evolution between man and nature. James O'Connor presents a more nuanced view in which Marx at best defended a conservationist defense of nature. I argue that such ecological views of Marx tend to overlook his abandonment of an ontology of nature as a totality of relations among physical objects with respect to their interactions and mutual preservation and order. He followed Kant in reducing nature, or the physical world, effectively to a regulative notion, thus reducing its value to a simply a heuristic one for judgments about and actions towards objects. But he also radicalized this reduction by envisaging nature only as a material field of fungible and consumable things, such that each thing is a mere locus of energy or force that human labor cannot substantively perfect but only change to a function. Labor in this view creates new arrangements of natural things for a singular ultimate purpose: the formation of associations of free labor. I conclude that Marx's thinking thus cannot be utilized to support an environmental philosophy, such as deep ecology or eco-socialism, that would posit any intrinsic value to nature. Ecological Marxists argue that Marx forged a view of nature compatible with more recent models of environmentalism. John Bellamy Foster argues that Marx ascribed an ecological value to nature by asserting a co-evolution between man and nature. James O'Connor presents a more nuanced view in which Marx at best defended a conservationist defense of nature. I argue that such ecological views of Marx tend to overlook his abandonment of an ontology of nature as a totality of relations among physical objects with respect to their interactions and mutual preservation and order. He followed Kant in reducing nature, or the physical world, effectively to a regulative notion, thus reducing its value to a simply a heuristic one for judgments about and actions towards objects. But he also radicalized this reduction by envisaging nature only as a material field of fungible and consumable things, such that each thing is a mere locus of energy or force that human labor cannot substantively perfect but only change to a function. Labor in this view creates new arrangements of natural things for a singular ultimate purpose: the formation of associations of free labor. I conclude that Marx's thinking thus cannot be utilized to support an environmental philosophy, such as deep ecology or eco-socialism, that would posit any intrinsic value to nature.
作者 James Swindal
出处 《Frontiers of Philosophy in China》 2014年第3期358-369,共12页 中国哲学前沿(英文版)
关键词 Kant Marx ENGELS NATURE ECOLOGY Kant, Marx, Engels, nature, ecology
  • 相关文献

参考文献46

  • 1I will refrain from taking up the specific topic of how to differentiate between "nature" and "environment," which is beyond the scope of a paper of this length.
  • 2But I acknowledge that I am excluding not only earlier eighteenth-century versions of German Idealism, particularly in Wolff and Leibniz, but also its extensions, after the time of Marx, into the later nineteenth and early twentieth centuries. I also shall focus primarily on Capital in my analysis, and thus not focus on the view of nature in The German Ideology, which was written primarily by Engels.
  • 3Foster does acknowledge Alfred Schmidt's rejection of any compatibility between materialism and dialectics (see Foster 2000, 64, 245; Schmidt 1973).
  • 4O'Conllor does speak of the "biological exploitation" that Marx failed fully to capture (see O'Connor 1998, 337).
  • 5Ostensibly this mirrors the distinction between the quantitative (abstract) and the qualitative (concrete).
  • 6See Wendling (2011, 374-76). O'Connor notes that thermodynamics has not been integrated into historical materialism (see O'Connor 1998, 125; Marx 1990, 289).
  • 7His early labor theory of value, inspired by Ricardo, considers not a set of values but rather the origin of a singular value: the reproduction of the human species.
  • 8Foster maintains that humans both transform nature and are "capable of changing their relation to it through inventions" (see Foster 2000, 78).
  • 9Kojin Karatani and Slavoj Zi:ek both make reference to use of the term "parallax" in the Kantian sense.
  • 10All First Critique references will be to Smith (1965). I will place the A and B editions page citations directly into the text.

相关作者

内容加载中请稍等...

相关机构

内容加载中请稍等...

相关主题

内容加载中请稍等...

浏览历史

内容加载中请稍等...
;
使用帮助 返回顶部